Abbildungen der Seite
PDF
EPUB

standing these, the jury have found his publication a libel; and that, therefore, there is no ground for the interference of this Court.

But as it is of importance, that the rule of evidence which has been made a question, should not be left subject to doubt in any future case, it is thought proper that I should also declare the opinion of the judges upon the law, in this respect.

It has been insisted on for the defendant, that in a criminal proceeding, as well as in a civil action, a party charged with a libel, may give the truth of it in evidence. His counsel have contended that, this was the general rule of the Common Law, which may be inferred from the Statutes of Westminster, 2 Rich. 2. and I and 2 Phil. and Mary, all of which provide for the punishment of false tales only, and that therefore the publication of " true tales," however scandalous and malicious, was not then punishable. This, I believe to be a correct construction of these statutes, as to all of fences which come within them; but it does not follow from this, that they were declaratory of the only offences at Common Law, of the same nature, and that they recognize a common law right, to justify a libel, by giving the truth in evidence. The contrary may, I think, be fairly presumed; for, although on the trial of some offences under these statutes, the judges have said that the same were before punishable at Common Law, yet they do not say that it was not also a common law offence, to publish even 66 true tales," for a malicious purpose. These statutes, it appears, have prescribed new and more grievous punishments; it is most probable, therefore, that they only intended to punish in a greater degree, the publication of tales, which were aggravated by falsehood, and to leave the lesser offence to the common law remedy. This presumption is strengthened by the consideration, that all these statutes were made for special purposes. The first (Statute of Westminster) was made to suppress sedition. The Stat. of Rich. 2. was made to protect the great officers of the government; and the last, (1 and 2 P. and M.) was also made to suppress sedition.

But it is not necessary to explore the dark recesses of the ansient law, to ascertain this point. It has been ascertained for us No. XIII.

G

by those more eminently qualified than we are, for this great labour; by those who are our best guides in all our legal researches, and to whose steady and unerring light, we may more safely trust, than to any new lights of the present day. All the great expounders of the law, from Lord Coke, down to Mr. Justice Blackstone, have uniformly laid it down as a rule of the common law, that the truth of a libel cannot be given in evidence in a criminal proceeding; and this rule has never been departed from in a single instance. It is true, that a difference of opinion did, for some time exist among the English Judges, on the law respecting libels; but this was only the question, whether the Court or the Jury should decide on the criminal intent of the publication. The dispute was at last settled by the Stat. of 31 Geo. III. commonly called Mr. Fox's Act; and we think, correctly settled: for, we are all of opinion, that the statute was only declaratory of the old law. A jury has the unquestionable right to decide on the criminality of a libel, as far as the libel itself is the evidence of it. For this purpose, a defendant may read and rely on any part of it, to show an innocent motive and purpose in the publication; and this right was allowed to the defendant in the present case, in its fullest latitude.

But the law, at no time, and under no construction, has ever authorised a defendant, in a criminal proceeding, to justify a libel, by giving the truth of it in evidence. This has been invariably refused. It has been asserted, that the first case in which this was solemnly ruled, was decided in the Star Chamber; but as no case can be found, prior to that, in which it was otherwise ruled, it is reasonable to conclude, that this was not the creation of a new rule, but the observance only of an old one. And, even if it did originate in this odious and tyrannical court, yet it does not follow, that the rule itself is also odious and tyrannical.

The adherence to it by the common law courts, ever since, proves the contrary: they have given legitimacy to it as a common law rule; and its authority is further sanctioned by the justice and morality of its object. How many other rules are there of modern origin, and of less importance to the quiet and happiness of society, which are acknowledged to form a part of the common law, and from which we are not at liberty to depart?

It is a great error, to look to the first sources of the common law, for the purity of its principles. The best and purest of these, are of later accession. The sources of the common law, (except such parts as were derived from the laws of Rome) were shallow and muddy. In its downward course, it has been continually filtered and enlarged, by passing through courts of increased wisdom and science; and it is owing to these continued filterings and accessions, that we see it as it now is, a clear, wholesome, deep, and majestic stream. The most ancient decisions rest chiefly upon feudal principles, or upon reasons altogether barbarous and preposterous; these have been gradually disregarded; and we see more modern adjudications supported by such solid and rational grounds, that we may now say of the common law, with a very few exceptions, that nothing is law which is not reason.

But there is good cause to believe, that this rule did not originate in the Star Chamber, and was not the creature of that court. The rule was not peculiar to England: it existed long before. It made a part of the Roman law. We read in the pandects of Justinian, that "a defamer is not to be exempt from the punishment "due to the injury, although the libel contain nothing but what is "true. It is not permitted to make proof of facts, which are secret, "and which have been the foundation of the libel." The same rule was adopted by a special edict of France, in 1561; and it is also to be found in the Constitution of the Emperor Charles V. in these words: "Though the defamation were grounded on truth, yet the "defamer ought to be punished according to the power of the "judge." (Sec Inst. Justin. lib. 4. tit. 4. 2 Domat. B. 3. tit. 12. and also, Bayle's Dissertation on defamatory libels.)

It is most probable then, that this rule was derived from the civil law. We know, that for many centuries, this was the law of all Europe; and England was governed by it for nearly 400 years. Although the barbarians who successively invaded and possessed that country, introduced into it many of their own laws and customs, yet the maxims and principles of the Roman law were too deeply founded in reason and justice, to have been ever disused; and there is no doubt, that they compose now a large part of the common law of England. The celebrated Sir William Jones, has

said, "the pandects of Justinian, are a most valuable mine of judi"dicial knowledge. They give law at this hour to the greatest "part of Europe; and, though few English lawyers dare make "such an acknowledgment, the civil law is the true source of near"ly all our English laws, that are not founded off a feudal origin." (Letter to the governor general of India, in 1788)

I hope that the authority of this enlightened and profound searcher into antiquity, will satisfy the objection which was made to this rule, if it should happen to be of Roman origin. But this is not only the law of England, and probably of all Europe; it is the law also of most of the free States of America. It is the law of New-York, (as appears in the trial of Croswell) even in the exceptionable degree which Mr. Fox's Act was made to correct. It was the law of Pennsylvania; because the constitution of that state makes an exception to it in libels against public officers. And it must have been the law of Connecticut, previously to the Act of her legislature in 1804, or that Act would not have been made.*

I have so far considered the case on the ground of authority, and it would be sufficient for us to decide it on that ground only; for we are bound to declare the law, and to give it operation, whether it be founded on good or bad reasons. But, as there does not exist in the whole system of our laws, a rule better supported by reasons than the one under consideration, and as the counsel for the defendant have contended that those are not applicable to the state of our society-it is proper that I should take some notice of the objections made on this ground. I think indeed that the multiplied instances of the general adoption of the rule in every state of society, and under every form of government, afford sufficient proof of its being a rule both of general policy and morality. But as this rule is more fully evinced by the reasons assigned for it by the commentators on our laws, I will proceed to examine these. In 5. Rep.12.Lord Coke says, " a libel may be either "against a private man or against a magistrate. If it be made "against a private man, it deserves a severe punishment; for al"though a libel be against one, yet it excites all those of the same "family, kindred or society to revenge, and so tends to quarrels and “breaches of the peace, and may be the cause of the shedding of

* Not the law in Maryland.

[ocr errors]

"blood." He then proceeds to say, "it is not material whether "the libel be true, or whether the party libelled be of good or ill "fame; for in a settled government, a party grieved ought to ❝ complain for any injury done him in the ordinary course of larv, "and ought by no means to revenge himself either by libelling or "otherwise." The same reasons for not allowing the truth of a libel to be given in evidence, are laid down in numerous other authorities; but I shall only refer further to Mr. Just. Blackstone. In his 4th book, 150, he thus states the law, "it is immaterial with "respect to the essence of a libel, whether the matter of it be true "or false, since the provocation and not the falsity is the thing to "be punished criminally; though doubtless the falsehood of it may aggravate its guilt and enhance the punishment." "In a "civil suit, a libel must appear to be false as well as scandalous " for if the charge be true, the party has received no injury, and "has no ground to demand a compensation for himself whatever "offence it may be against the public. But in a criminal prosecu"cution, the tendency which all libels have to create animosities, "and to disturb the public peace is the sole consideration of the law."

Here then we see it distinctly laid down, that although the falsehood of a libel, will aggravate the offence, yet the offence is complete without it? but a libel is an offence, not because it is false, but because it tends to provoke quarrels and private revenge, which is an usurpation of the public authority; that the objects therefore of punishing a libel, are to preserve the public peace and to enforce a due submission to the laws. Can it be seriously contended, that these objects are not applicable to our state of socie ty? It appears to me, that every reflecting mind must allow that they are peculiarly necessary to a free government. The preservation of the public peace, and the prevention of private vengeance. in any form, are the very foundation of civil liberty, which could not be said to be fully enjoyed, unless these great ends were fully secured. It is for this reason that the sending a challenge is a high offence. This too is punishable, only because it is a provocation to a breach of the public peace. It is also a public offence, to sieze. by force one's own property, because it is not lawful for any man to redress his own wrongs. If, therefore, a man forcibly takes

« ZurückWeiter »